Carter Smith

Position Paper

 

A COLLISION OF IMAGES, A KALEIDOSCOPE:
ON GLEBER’S “THE CITY OF
MODERNITY”

 

 

Simultaneously offering a reading of Swann’s Way and the flaneur’s gaze, Walter Benjamin observes, in The Arcades Project, the “principle of flanerie” (420) in the following passage from Proust:

 

“[S]uddenly a roof, a gleam of sunlight reflected from a stone, the smell of a road would make me stop still, to enjoy the special pleasure that each of them gave me, and also because they appeared to be concealing, beneath what my eyes could see, something which they invited me to approach and take from them, but which, despite all my efforts, I never managed to discover.” (qtd. in Benjamin 420)

 

Though Gleber’s analysis in “The City of Modernity” focuses more on the conditions of flanerie than on the pleasure and enjoyment of the flaneur, like Proust, she is concerned with “what [the] eyes could see.” And, according to her argument, the late nineteenth-century city bombarded the eyes of the city dweller with stimuli such that the visual register becomes “a primary factor in the quality of his urban life” (24).

 

Indeed, for Gleber, a study of the city as a visual field is the most useful way to understand the flaneur’s walk through it. One of the salutary features of this approach is the way in which it relates changes in the act of looking to changes in material culture. Electric light, by making the cityscape visible at night, creates an environment in which “the public sphere is perceived as an interior space in the street” (33). Window displays and poster advertisements are but two examples of the “rapid proliferation of visual stimuli in the street” (36). Everywhere one looked, Gleber argues, there was something to be seen.

 

To account for the psychological impact of this proliferation of visual stimuli, Gleber turns to Georg Simmel’s 1903 work “The Metropolis and Mental Life.” Simmel argues that, as a result of increased stimulation, modern visual sensibility is informed primarily by differentiation, that “the essentially intellectualist character of the mental life of the metropolis” (qtd. in Gleber 25) can be attributed to the mental processing of images.

 

“[T]he mental life of the metropolis”: what a reader might take as an idiom roughly equivalent to “mental life in the metropolis,” Gleber  later emphasizes in a paraphrase of Simmel. Of the dandy, the snob, and the flaneur, she writes that “these urban dispositions in the city’s mental life may correspond to three distinct types of ‘social characters’” (25 emphasis added). The difference between mental life in the metropolis and the mental life of the metropolis has everything to do with the flaneur’s sensibility. Is his sensibility, after all, comprised only of the specular?

 

As an amusement for the eye--one that produces an ever-changing image from small shifts in its constituent elements--the kaleidoscope is an appropriate metaphor for the flux of Gleber’s city. The city is a “kaleidoscope of signs”--signs such as price tags, traffic lights, and advertisements--that “convey the value of things while at the same time suggesting their value as signs” (40). It seems to me that Proust’s emphasis on the unknowability of what lies beneath signs has something to add to the image of the flaneur that we get in “The City of Modernity,” something for which Gleber possibly accounts in her trope of the kaleidoscope. For, at the end of the essay, she shifts the terms of the comparison, claiming that the flaneur’s “sensitivity to the objects and obsessions of [. . .] modernity renders him a significant kaleidoscope of his time” (41). The statement echoes an earlier paraphrase of Simmel: “A medium embodied in a human sensitivity, [the flaneur] specializes in the perception and formulation of the city’s heterogenous mental life” (29). In the shift from city-as-kaleidoscope to flaneur-as-kaleidoscope, does Gleber suggest a range of city experiences that extend beyond the visual?